categories - Category Theory list
 help / color / mirror / Atom feed
* Is Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory inconsistent?
@ 1999-04-01 12:10 Paul Taylor
  1999-04-01 15:52 ` Mike Oliver
  1999-04-01 20:23 ` Dusko Pavlovic
  0 siblings, 2 replies; 3+ messages in thread
From: Paul Taylor @ 1999-04-01 12:10 UTC (permalink / raw)
  To: categories


		IS ZERMELO-FRAENKEL SET THEORY INCONSISTENT?

At the end of this message is a sketch of an argument that leads to
the conclusion that Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory is inconsistent.

The impact on mathematics is not as devastating as the incautious
observer might suppose.   Recall that ZERMELO set theory (1908), which
is essentially equivalent to the categorists' notion of ELEMENTARY TOPOS
with natural numbers and the axiom of choice,  is adequate for
most of the purposes of mathematics, though not, as I shall try to
explain, logic (and theoretical computer science).

ZERMELO-FRAENKEL set theory is the extension of this system by the
axiom-scheme of REPLACEMENT, which was first formulated by Adolf
(later Abraham) Fraenkel, Nels Lennes and Thoralf Skolem in 1922,
although Dimitry Mirimanoff already had something of the idea in 1917.
Notice that this is some two decades after the appearance of the famous
"antinomies" of set theory, so presumably the set theorists' guard had
dropped by that time, and they had begun again to assert megalomaniac
axioms.   On the other hand, it is a decade before the second generation
of paradoxical results, Godel's incompleteness theorem and Turing's
unsolvability of the Halting Problem.

Whenever I see set theory books in a library or bookshop, I turn to
the index to find out what they have to say about Replacement.  Usually
there is some trivial result, such as the existence of what categorists
call image factorisation, that could have been proved from Zermelo's
axioms with a little more facility in set-theoretic constructions.

The basic use of Replacement, that you will find in the better set theory
books, is the recursive construction of sets (in substance -- types or
objects to type-theorists and categorists -- rather than their names).

For example, Mostowski's theorem states that every well founded extensional
binary relation < is isomorphic to the membership relation for a unique
transitive set.  This is found, recursively, by means of the formula
	f(x)  =   { f(y) |  y < x },
which also provides the extensional reflection (quotient) of any well
founded relation. In fact the latter result (where the quotient relation
is merely another relation, rather than a membership relation) can be
proved using the topos or Zermelo axioms alone, and not Replacement [1],
although there are categorical generalisations of this that certainly do
need Replacement.

Richard Montague [2] proved a result that should have been taken as a
warning of the perilous nature of Replacement, though I suspect that
Montague's personal eccentricities may have been the reason why he was
ignored. ZF can prove the consistency, not only of Zermelo set theory (Z)
itself, but also of Z extended by any single theorem of ZF.

Adrian Mathias has claimed [3] that Bourbaki was "ignorant" of Replacement,
ie that it did not occur in "Theorie des Ensembles" [4].   Although
Bourbaki is hardly very clear on this matter, it does include a
version of Replacement in its axioms, indeed one that is in widespread
use in category theory and other parts of mathematics, namely that one
can form the UNION of any SET-INDEXED FAMILY of SETS.

One application of N-indexed unions in theoretical computer science is
Scott's "D-infinity" construction of models of the untyped lambda calculus.
Starting from any domain D0=D, one may form its function-space D1=(D0->D0),
and similarly D2=(D1->D1), etc., linking these together with embedding-
projection pairs.  If D was one of the examples of L-domains, having a
pair of elements with infinitely many minimal upper bounds, then one can
show (classically) that D-infinity has the cardinality of a model of
Zermelo set theory, so need not exist within such a model unless it also
satisfies Replacement.

These two ways of seeing Replacement have a common theme: we use N-indexed
or transfinite unions to unfold a free(ish) model of one logic within
a model of another.

Having seen this in the context of a messy domain-theoretic construction,
we may think in a more disciplined way about free models of the lambda
calculus, the topos axioms, etc.  In fact, there is no difficulty in
constructing these models, as they are merely TERM ALGEBRAS.  The problem
lies in proving that the term algebra has the universal (initiality)
property that qualifies it as "free":

	Let S be the universe (the category of ZF-sets, for example)
	and F the term algebra (internal to S) for the logic L.
	Suppose that S itself is a model of L.

	Then there is a unique interpretation functor []:F->S
	that takes each syntactic operation of F (eg prod(a,b))
	to the semantics ([a] x [b]) in S.

It is merely unique up to unique isomorphism if the L-structure in S is
defined by universal properties rather than being chosen.

This initiality property may also be expressed type-theoretically.
Per Martin-Lof [5] introduced objects with such a property, called UNIVERSES,
observing the analogy with Replacement.  This point of view stresses that
the above property is a RECURSION SCHEME.

Let me explain how I came to realise that the existence of []:F->S depends,
in general, on Replacement.

There is an amazingly simple but incredibly powerful argument, due to
Peter Freyd and known variously as (Artin-Wraith) glu(e)ing, sconing,
the Freyd cover, logical relations and other names.  It is based on some
very elementary categorical investigations of a certain comma category 
involving F and S.   This argument has been developed rather a long way
(the most recent paper that I know of is [6]), and we are pretty close
to having a purely categorical proof of the strong normalisation theorem
for lambda calculi that, unlike the syntactic proofs, is completely
generic with regard to the calculus in question.

Freyd originally showed that the terminal object (1) of the free topos (F)
is projective, and more generally the "global sections functor" 
F(1,-) : F -> S preserves colimits.   In particular, it preserves the
initial object (0), which is categorical jargon for saying that S proves
the consistency of F, because the S-set of F-morphisms 1->0 is the
initial (empty) S-set.

I found this suspicious, because the punch-line of Andre Joyal's 1973
(but as yet unpublished and unavailable) categorical proof of Godel's
incompleteness theorem is that such a functor F(1,-) : F -> S does *not*
preserve the initial object.

The more careful amongst categorists ought also to be suspicious when
I speak of "a functor F(1,-) or [] : F -> S" where F is an INTERNAL 
category in S.   The meaning that we must give to this phrase is that
it is "syntactic sugar" for a certain FIBRATION  p: V -> F, where V is
also an internal category and p and internal functor in S.

This brings us back to the relationship between Replacement as a recursive
construction of objects and Replacement as infinitary colimits:
"p: V -> F"  is the colimit (in a 2-category whose objects are fibrations)
of a recursively defined diagram vaguely similar to that which gives Scott's
D-infinity.

I have come to the conclusion that attempts to define "colimits" such as
this are inherently circular: what, after all, does it mean to have a
"cocone" to test such an alleged colimit?

My categorical formulation of Replacement speaks about fibrations
and smaller colimits defined internally in the style of Benabou.
This is to be found in the final section (9.5) of my book [7],
Section 7.7 of which also gives an account of Freyd's gluing construction.

This book is officially due to be published in mid-May,  but it is
already in stock (and I have my own copy in front of me), and is
available direct from the publishers at 50 pounds (inclusive of overland
postage and packing).   Please contact
	Richard Knott,
	email:  rknott@cup.cam.ac.uk
	fax:    +44 1223 315 052
	tel:    +44 1223 325 916 (but other methods are preferable)
	snail:  Cambridge University Press, The Edinburgh Building,
                Shaftesbury Road, Cambridge, CB2 2RU, UK
with your address and credit card number.  (2.50 pounds extra for airmail.)

Having seen that Replacement provides a UNIFORM way of proving
consistency of any fragment of logic, we come at last to the
inconsistency argument:

	Let L(0) be Zermelo set theory
	(or the axioms for an elementary topos).

	For each n,  let L(n+1)  be   L(n)  plus
	as much of the axiom-scheme of replacement as is needed
	to justify the gluing construction that shows that

		L(n+1) |-  ``L(n) is consistent.''

	Now let   L(infinity)   be   the union of  L(n) over n:N.

	If    L(infinity) |- false   then   L(n) |- false   for some n.

	But   L(infinity) |-  ``L(n) is consistent,''

	so    L(infinity)   proves its OWN consistency,
	contradicting Godel's theorem.

	However,  L(infinity)   has a standard non-trivial interpretation
	in Zermelo--Fraenkel set theory, which is therefore inconsistent.

[1] Paul Taylor, Intuitionistic Sets and Ordinals, JSL 61 (1996) 705-44

[2] Richard Montague, Fraenkel's Addition to the Axioms of Zermelo,
    pp 91--114 of Bar-Hillel, et al., eds., Essays on the Foundations of 
    Mathematics, Magnes Press, Hebrew University, 1966 (distributed
    by Oxford University Press).

[3] Adrian Mathias, The Ignorance of Bourbaki, Mathematical Intelligencer,
    14 (1992) 4-13.

[4] Nicolas Bourbaki, Elements de Mathematique XXII: Theories des Ensembles,
    Livre I, Structures, Hermann, 1957 (English translation 1968).

[5] Per Martin-Lof, An Intuitionistic Theory of Types: Predicative part,
    pp 73--118 in Rose and Sheperdson, eds., Logic Colloquium '73,
    North-Holland, Studies in Logic and the Foundations of Mathematics #80,
    1975

[6] Djordje Cubric, Peter Dybjer and Philip Scott, Normalisation and the 
    Yoneda Embedding, MSCS 8 (1998) 153--192.

[7] Paul Taylor, Practical Foundations of Mathematics, Cambridge University
    Press, Cambridge Studies in Advanced Mathematics #59, xii+572pp, 1999.

    http://www.dcs.qmw.ac.uk/~pt/Practical_Foundations/

Paul Taylor  <pt@dcs.qmw.ac.uk>  19990401

This message may be copied elsewhere,
ON CONDITION that it is quoted in its ENTIRETY.



^ permalink raw reply	[flat|nested] 3+ messages in thread

* Re: Is Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory inconsistent?
  1999-04-01 12:10 Is Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory inconsistent? Paul Taylor
@ 1999-04-01 15:52 ` Mike Oliver
  1999-04-01 20:23 ` Dusko Pavlovic
  1 sibling, 0 replies; 3+ messages in thread
From: Mike Oliver @ 1999-04-01 15:52 UTC (permalink / raw)
  To: categories



Paul Taylor wrote:
>         Now let   L(infinity)   be   the union of  L(n) over n:N.
> 
>         If    L(infinity) |- false   then   L(n) |- false   for some n.
> 
>         But   L(infinity) |-  ``L(n) is consistent,''
> 
>         so    L(infinity)   proves its OWN consistency,
>         contradicting Godel's theorem.

How do you conclude, from the fact that L(infinity) |- "L(n) is consistent", that
L(n) is in fact consistent?

Generally, if T1 |- "T2 is consistent", then to conclude "T2 is consistent",
we use the following argument:  Suppose T2 is inconsistent.  Then
there is some proof by which T2 |- false.  Assuming T1 is strong enough
to formalize the deductive system being used, then it follows
that T1 |- "T2 is inconsistent".   But by hypothesis, T1 |- "T2 is consistent",
therefore T1 is inconsistent.

But this is not a contradiction unless we were already *assuming* the
consistency of T1 !  I.e. it follows from T1+Con(T1) that
if T1 |- Con(T2), then Con(T2), but it does *not* in general
follow from T1 alone.

So the step from
	L(infinity) |- "L(n) is consistent"
to
	L(n) is consistent

cannot be formalized in any obvious way in L(infinity), and therefore
you cannot (again in any obvious way) conclude
L(infinity) |- "L(infinity) is consistent."

-- 
Disclaimer:  I could be wrong -- but I'm not.  (Eagles, "Victim of Love")

Finger for PGP public key, or visit http://www.math.ucla.edu/~oliver.
1500 bits, fingerprint AE AE 4F F8 EA EA A6 FB  E9 36 5F 9E EA D0 F8 B9



^ permalink raw reply	[flat|nested] 3+ messages in thread

* Re: Is Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory inconsistent?
  1999-04-01 12:10 Is Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory inconsistent? Paul Taylor
  1999-04-01 15:52 ` Mike Oliver
@ 1999-04-01 20:23 ` Dusko Pavlovic
  1 sibling, 0 replies; 3+ messages in thread
From: Dusko Pavlovic @ 1999-04-01 20:23 UTC (permalink / raw)
  To: CATEGORIES

>      Let L(0) be Zermelo set theory (or the axioms for an elementary topos).
>
>         For each n,  let L(n+1)  be   L(n)  plus
>         as much of the axiom-scheme of replacement as is needed
>         to justify the gluing construction that shows that
>
>                 L(n+1) |-  ``L(n) is consistent.''
>
>         Now let   L(infinity)   be   the union of  L(n) over n:N.
>
>         If    L(infinity) |- false   then   L(n) |- false   for some n.
>
>         But   L(infinity) |-  ``L(n) is consistent,''
>
>         so    L(infinity)   proves its OWN consistency,
>         contradicting Godel's theorem.
>
>         However,  L(infinity)   has a standard non-trivial interpretation
>         in Zermelo--Fraenkel set theory, which is therefore inconsistent.

i think there is a gap is in the step

        L(infinity) |- "L(n) is consistent"
        so L(infinity) proves its OWN consistency

formalized in a suitable category of theories and interpretations, paul's
construction, if i understand it correctly, refers to the colimit of the tower

        L(0) --> FL(0)  --> FFL(0)  -->...

where FX = X + replacement_X, so that FX |- "X is consistent".

IF the colimit of this tower, paul's L(infinity), were a fixpoint of F, THEN it
would indeed prove its own consistency. but it doesn't seem to be a fixpoint:
the restrictions of the replacement to L(0), FL(0) etc. do not imply the
replacement for L(infinity).

btw, i bought paul's book and warmly recommend it.

-- dusko






^ permalink raw reply	[flat|nested] 3+ messages in thread

end of thread, other threads:[~1999-04-01 20:23 UTC | newest]

Thread overview: 3+ messages (download: mbox.gz / follow: Atom feed)
-- links below jump to the message on this page --
1999-04-01 12:10 Is Zermelo-Fraenkel set theory inconsistent? Paul Taylor
1999-04-01 15:52 ` Mike Oliver
1999-04-01 20:23 ` Dusko Pavlovic

This is a public inbox, see mirroring instructions
for how to clone and mirror all data and code used for this inbox;
as well as URLs for NNTP newsgroup(s).