categories - Category Theory list
 help / color / mirror / Atom feed
* Reddy's question
@ 1998-03-03 12:32 Peter Freyd
  0 siblings, 0 replies; 2+ messages in thread
From: Peter Freyd @ 1998-03-03 12:32 UTC (permalink / raw)
  To: categories

Uday Reddy poses the following (with a few changes in notation]:

>Consider a monoid  <M,*,e>  in a CCC.  The operations of interest
>are natural transformations  E:[-,M] -> M  that satisfy the
>following equations (in the internal language of the CCC):
>
>               E_A(\x.e)  =  e
>         E_A(\x. a * gx)  =  a * E_A(g)
>         E_A(\x. gx * a)  =  E_A(g) * a
>    E_A(\x. E_B(\y.hxy))  =  E_B(\y. E_A(\x.hxy))

I wonder if naturality is really desired: it would seem to force  M  to
be trivial. By the familiar Yoneda-lemma argument, E  must be constant
as far as the "points" of  [A,M]  are concerned. (Actually one doesn't
need the argument, just the lemma itself; consider the transformation
that  E  induces between set-valued functors  (-,M) -> (1,M); Yoneda
says it must be constant.) The condition

    E_A(\x.e)  =  e

forces just which constant it is. That is, for any  f:A -> M  it will
be the case that  E_A  will send  f  to  e.

But then either condition

    E_A(\x. a * gx) = a * E_A(g)

or

    E_A(\x. gx * a) = E_A(g) * a

will force  M  to be trivial. (It's clear in the \-calculus notation.
But that argument would be implicitly using the fact that  E_A  is
constant and we officially know only that it's constant on points.
So take, say, the second condition. It says in diagrammatic language:


              1 x K                 P            [A,*]
   [A,M] x M  -----> [A,M] x [A,M] ---> [A,MxM]  -----> [A,M]

         |                                                |
         |  E_A x 1_M                                     |  E_A
         |                                                |
                                    *
       M x M   ---------------------------------------->  M


where  K  is the standard "constant-map" operator that's adjoint to
the projection  AxM -> M  and  P  is the standard operator that
defines  MxM  (given products in Set). Specialize to  A = M  and
precompose with  <f,1>: M -> [M,M] x M  where  f  doesn't matter. If
the commutative rectangle above is chased clockwise one obtains the
map constantly valued  e. Chased counterclockwise one obtains the
identity map. And, of course, it didn't matter what  f  is.)




^ permalink raw reply	[flat|nested] 2+ messages in thread

* Re: Reddy's question
@ 1998-03-04  4:59 Uday S. Reddy
  0 siblings, 0 replies; 2+ messages in thread
From: Uday S. Reddy @ 1998-03-04  4:59 UTC (permalink / raw)
  To: categories; +Cc: reddy

Response by Peter Freyd to a question of mine:

> >Consider a monoid  <M,*,e>  in a CCC.  The operations of interest
> >are natural transformations  E:[-,M] -> M  that satisfy the
> >following equations (in the internal language of the CCC):
> >
> >               E_A(\x.e)  =  e
> >         E_A(\x. a * gx)  =  a * E_A(g)
> >         E_A(\x. gx * a)  =  E_A(g) * a
> >    E_A(\x. E_B(\y.hxy))  =  E_B(\y. E_A(\x.hxy))
> 
> I wonder if naturality is really desired: it would seem to force  M  to
> be trivial. 

Indeed!  (Peter Johnstone and Dusko Pavlovic also pointed out that I
went wrong in asking for naturality.)  Something got lost in
abstracting from my application domain.  My examples had additional
parameters which made naturality possible.  But, discarding those
parameters in the interest of abstration seems to have produced a
statement that is quite impossible to satisfy.  My apologies.

Dusko Pavlovic pointed out some of what we could do once we discard
the naturality condition.  The second and third equations can be
regarded as naturality properties by thinking of M and [A,M] as
categories and E_A as a functor.  (That is good, because it singles
out the first equation as a "pretender."  So, I shouldn't be worried
when it breaks.)

On the other hand, I don't know what to make of the fourth equation.
It says that for E_A to be an abstraction operator (tentatively using
Pavlovic's terminoloty), it has to commute with every other
abstraction operator E_B.  For one, that prevents me from giving a
local definition of what an abstraction operator is.  One needs to
define the whole collection of abstraction operators at one go.  (Now
that naturality is gone out the window, there is no reason to require
even that the family of operators be indexed by objects.  There could
be any number of maps for an object A.)  Secondly, looking at it from
the application point of view, there is something "intrinsic" about
these operators that makes them commute with each other.  It is not
really a property of the whole collection of operators.  The presence
or absence of another operator in the collection shouldn't matter.  I
really have no idea how to capture this kind of "uniformity" in the
commutativity property.  Some hyperdoctrine-like idea, perhaps?

Despite the fact the first equation doesn't hold in all toposes, I
think the example of the existential quantifier is an illuminating
one.  Evaluation at a particular point is a "degenerate" example in
that it also satisfies

      E_A(\x. fx * gx) = E_A(f) * E_A(g)

The existential quantifier gives a better intuition for the idea of
these operators.

Hope this explains the question better.

Uday Reddy



^ permalink raw reply	[flat|nested] 2+ messages in thread

end of thread, other threads:[~1998-03-04  4:59 UTC | newest]

Thread overview: 2+ messages (download: mbox.gz / follow: Atom feed)
-- links below jump to the message on this page --
1998-03-03 12:32 Reddy's question Peter Freyd
1998-03-04  4:59 Uday S. Reddy

This is a public inbox, see mirroring instructions
for how to clone and mirror all data and code used for this inbox;
as well as URLs for NNTP newsgroup(s).